sábado, 17 de junio de 2017

BioEdge: Autonomy: a short history of a big idea | BioEdge | Sunday, June 18, 2017 |

BioEdge: An urgent need for palliative care as the world turns grey

| BioEdge | Sunday, June 18, 2017 |



Autonomy: a short history of a big idea
     
“The strongest arguments in favour of physician-assisted suicide are respect for autonomy, justice, compassion, honesty, individual liberty and transparency.” This is a sentence drawn from a press release issued by the European Society of Anaesthesiology, which debated PAS at a conference in Geneva earlier this month. But it could have come from almost any medical ethics textbook. Respect for autonomy is a cornerstone of contemporary bioethics – and like all good cornerstones, it is firmly fixed and seldom tested.

However, an historical account of the notion in the journal Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy questions whether it is necessary or coherent or beneficent. Toni Saad, of the Cardiff University School of Medicine, in Wales, concludes that:

it is not necessary to embrace an ethic of autonomy in order to guard patients from coercion or paternalism, and that, on the contrary, the dominance of autonomy threatens to undermine those very things which have helped doctors come to view and respect their patients as persons.
This is a daring attack on a deeply entrenched principle, one which will require many salvos to demolish, but Saad makes a good fist of it.

First, he points out that the Hippocratic tradition in ancient medicine contained the germ of the notion of the modern notion of autonomy; it was not completely paternalistic and chauvinistic. For instance, there is evidence that disclosure of information, choice of physicians, informed consent and medical truth-telling were all present in the practice of good physicians. “This suggests that a conscious awareness of the concept of autonomy is not always necessary for good medical practice.”

In the most substantial part of the essay Saad examines the Enlightenment legacy of Rousseau, Kant, and J.S. Mill. This is too complex and lengthy to summarise here, but the upshot is that the hallmark of authentic moral actions was free choice, not the content of the action.

Thus, logical inconsistency becomes the only immorality, and distaste for inconsistency the measure of morality; rationality has no content beyond itself; ethics is reduced to reason and must therefore remain agnostic about what is good and evil.
He then moves on to the post-War development of bioethics, which originated in the worlds horror at Nazi atrocities. The Nuremberg Code is a key document which stresses the importance of free and informed consent.

A key figure in the bioethics of the 1970s was Paul Ramsey, who was “unabashedly Christian” and set the agenda for later developments – suggesting, too, that “autonomy” may not be needed as a guarantor of good medical care. However, his influence faded with the widespread popularity of the four elements of Beauchamp and Childress’s principlism in the 1980s. They “emptied the words ‘respect’ and ‘person’ of their meaning, so that autonomy per se becomes that which is respected, not persons.” Although their framework appeared merely to enshrine conventional ethical views, Saad argues that it made autonomy central. It “possesses the seeds of its own destruction because so little cannot be justified by appeal to [respect for autonomy]” – from organ retrieval from living patients to limiting conscientious objection.

Although competing ethical traditions exist, respect for autonomy has quickly become the dominant ethical framework. Why? Saad fingers moral fragmentation:

Bioethics, with its emphasis on autonomy, is the inheritor or of an increasingly thinning concept of human goods. Thus, the principle of RFA and its tendency to dominate contemporary ethical discourse is symptomatic of an atrophied conception of human flourishing, and a consequent shift towards formally rational debate.  Since theorists cannot agree on what is good, they will reach for the few remaining available principles, and thereby lock themselves in to a formally rational and inevitably reductive debate. This is the ground upon which autonomy ethics flourishes. Indeed, nothing but autonomy can grow upon this soil, which means the inevitable decimation of diversity in bioethical discourse, and maybe even moral famine.
It is a fascinating essay which deserves to be widely read.

Like our coverage of bioethics? If so, could we ask you for a favour? BioEdge takes a lot of time and hard work to produce. We do it because we think that our readers deserve to get the full picture of complex issues like surrogacy, euthanasia and stem cell research. We try to offer ideas to ponder and debate. To continue enhancing the conversation we need your support.

If every fan of BioEdge donated just $10, our future would be much more secure.

    DONATE NOW   


Bioedge

Sunday, June 18, 2017

A Massachusetts woman has been found guilty of involuntary manslaughter in a case which was reported across the United States and could affect the debate about assisted suicide.
In 2014 Michelle Carter, then 17, used phone calls and text messages to bully her boyfriend, Conrad Roy III, 18, into asphyxiating himself in his car.
Their relationship was a bizarre one. Although they lived only an hour away from each other, they met in Florida on family holidays. Thereafter they only met each other a handful of times. But they texted each other incessantly, especially about Roy’s desire to kill himself. Ms Carter encouraged him.
However, when he was sitting in his car and the fumes were building up, he got out, clearly wanting to live. She instructed him to get back in. He did and he died.
There are two schools of thought about Ms Carter’s bullying. Most people would agree with the judge that she had a duty to try to save Roy’s life and acted in a “wanton and reckless” manner.
But others, while acknowledging that her words were reprehensible, point out that Massachusetts has no law against assisted suicide and that words are not bullets. They argue that her incitement was protected free speech.  
The American Civil Liberties Union has yet another reason why Ms Carter should have been acquitted: “If allowed to stand, Ms. Carter’s conviction could chill important and worthwhile end-of-life discussions between loved ones.” In other words, this throws sand in the gears of legalising assisted suicide.
What do you think? 


Michael Cook
Editor
BioEdge



NEWS THIS WEEK
 
by Michael Cook | Jun 17, 2017
New research shows that the need for palliative care could increase by 40% by 2040
 
by Michael Cook | Jun 17, 2017
Do we really need 'autonomy' to explain why people should be decently treated?
 
by Michael Cook | Jun 17, 2017
How a public relations campaign made the FDA approve a bad drug
 
by Xavier Symons | Jun 17, 2017
We can never set aside the risk of a euthanasia market.
 
by Xavier Symons | Jun 17, 2017
A growing number of Silicon Valley companies are sponsoring employees to “freeze their eggs”.
 
by Xavier Symons | Jun 17, 2017
The death of an 8-year-old boy has sparked debate about organ procurement.


BioEdge
Suite 12A, Level 2 | 5 George St | North Strathfield NSW 2137 | Australia
Phone: +61 2 8005 8605
Mobile: 0422-691-615

No hay comentarios:

Publicar un comentario